Essay Market Morals Related

Still, how far do we want to go down this path?

• Is it right that prisoners in Santa Ana, Calif., can pay $90 per night for an upgrade to a cleaner, nicer jail cell?

• Should the really sell visas? A $500,000 investment will buy foreigners the right to immigrate.

• Should have gone ahead with a proposal to sell naming rights to its state parks? wondered in 2003 whether Walden Pond might become Pond.

• Should strapped towns accept virtually free police cars that come laden with advertising on the sides? Such a deal was negotiated and then ultimately collapsed, but at least one town does sell advertising on its police cars.

“The marketization of everything means that people of affluence and people of modest means lead increasingly separate lives,” Sandel writes. “We live and work and shop and play in different places. Our children go to different schools. You might call it the skyboxification of American life. It’s not good for democracy, nor is it a satisfying way to live.”

“Do we want a society where everything is up for sale? Or are there certain moral and civic goods that markets do not honor and money cannot buy?”

This issue goes to the heart of fairness in our country. There has been much discussion recently about economic inequality, but almost no conversation about the way the spread of markets nurtures a broader, systemic inequality.

We do, of course, place some boundaries on markets. I can’t buy the right to cut off your leg for my amusement. Americans can sell blood, but (perhaps mistakenly) we don’t allow markets for kidneys and other organs, even though that would probably save lives.

Wealthy people can, in effect, buy access to the president at a $40,000-a-plate dinner, but they can’t purchase a Medal of Freedom. A major political donor can sometimes buy an ambassadorship, but not to an important country.

Where to draw the lines limiting the role of markets isn’t clear to me, but I’m pretty sure that we’ve already gone too far. I’m offended when governments auction naming rights to public property or sell special access, even if only to fast lanes on a highway or better cells in a jail. It is one thing for to have first class and coach. It is quite another for government to offer first class and coach in the essential services that government provides.

Where would this stop? Do we let people pay to get premium police and fire protection? Do we pursue an idea raised by Judge Richard Posner to auction off the right to adopt children?

We already have tremendous inequality in our country: The richest 1 percent of Americans own more wealth than the bottom 90 percent, according to the . But we do still have a measure of equality before the law — equality in our basic dignity — and that should be priceless.

“ fundamentalism,” to use the term popularized by George Soros, is gaining ground. It’s related to the glorification of wealth over the last couple of decades, to the celebration of opulence, and to the emergence of a new aristocracy. Market fundamentalists assume a measure of social Darwinism and accept that laissez-faire is always optimal.

That’s the dogma that helped lead to bank deregulation and the current economic mess. And anyone who honestly believes that low taxes and unfettered free markets are always best should consider moving to ’s tribal areas. They are a triumph of limited government, negligible taxes, no “burdensome regulation” and free markets for everything from drugs to AK-47s.

If you’re infatuated with unfettered free markets, just visit Waziristan.

Continue reading the main story

Today’s offering in our Timeless Essay series affords our readers the opportunity to explore trans-economic values and the necessity of returning to them lest we bring about our own economic demise. —W. Winston Elliott III, Publisher

Nikolai Lenin said that when the time came to hang the capitalists, they would trip over each other to sell the communists the necessary rope. One is remind­ed also of the similar case of a Canadian mining firm whose owner, in order to keep the business, worked with Castro and generously donated money to his Young Communist League. And currently, we have the example of capitalists, including former high-ranking government officials, blithely trading with Communist China despite its human rights violations and aggressive military build-up. What do these examples have in common? They illustrate the effect of actions based on self-interest alone, self-interest turned loose from any anchor in morality or community values, thus proving it is not an adequate basis of economic or social organization.

The solution of the problem, of course, is not found in any form of collectivism. Rather, it lies in limiting the sphere of legitimate market activity so that it harmonizes with the rest of the community and with other values and indeed with itself. As will be argued here, in a properly understood sense, market limitation is a logical necessity. It is akin to the problem of political liberty which James Madison identified in Federalist No. 63 that “liberty may be endangered by the abuses of liberty as well as by the abuses of pow­er….” What is true of political liberty is also true of economic liberty.

To protect the market system against these destructive abuses, a commitment to permanent values is required by market participants, both consumers and producers, and to what German economist Wilhelm Roepke called a “terror regime of decency,” as well as to a public policy rooted in that decency. To do this, I want to consider the market with some of its blemish­es and issues relating to the role of moral values. There are three interrelated aspects to emphasize: (1) the failures of pure self-interest; (2) the nature of the relationship between market activity and morality; and (3) the question of the end-state vs. proceduralist views.

The Failures of Pure Self-Interest (Social Traps)

Adam Smith

A free market system is based on the assumption that the collective result of individuals pursuing their own self-interest is good. Adam Smith is famous for his dictum that we do not expect our meat from the benevolence of the butcher but from a regard for his own interest. Precisely so; yet, the fact remains that this assumption is not always valid. Many of the present policy problems are the direct outgrowth of a dogmatic version of this truth maintained even in the face of counter-examples which Adam Smith would have been the first to recognize.

Consider three cases. In a depression, as each employer tries to survive in the face of a diminishing demand, consulting only his self-interest, he lays off employees. But if all or a large number of employers do that, total demand declines even more and so requires more lay-offs. The collec­tive result of the individual decisions is unwanted even though each decision-maker helped bring it about. Similarly, in the familiar case of a “run on the bank” of by-gone days, one or a few withdrawals was not a problem, but if all or many suddenly withdrew their deposits, the results were disastrous for the bank—a result no one wanted, but which each one helped bring about. And as a final example, if we accept Talbot Page’s analysis, entrepre­neurs try to evade (externalize) costs whenever they can by exploiting weaknesses in the property rights system, especially in their choice of technology. In the current jargon, they try to socialize costs while, of course, still privatizing benefits. This means passing the costs off onto the environment, the general public, or the taxpay­er. Cost avoidance is arguably an impor­tant aspect of the firm’s idea of “efficiency,” but it is obviously not consistent with the economist’s definition of price efficiency which requires that the price reflect all of the relative benefits and costs. Thus, a higher product price may be the more efficient one. However, as each entrepreneur evades costs and pursues only his own self-interest, the cost “efficiency” of his firm may go up, but the efficiency of the market goes down.

To conclude this first point, if we are told that we are to maximize our self-interest in each specific transaction and that we are not to look out for the other guy or the common good and other intangibles, then it is not surprising to see not only how the failures described above come about, but also how they, or many like them, are maintained. And if we further tell people, as one George Mason University economist did to college students not long ago, that greed, in the sense of getting more things for oneself, is the noblest human motivation, then we cannot but believe these failures will grow worse in both frequency and intensity. And the success of this propaganda may be the biggest market failure of them all. If pure self-interest is not always beneficial or rational collectively, we must rely on something more.

Markets Presuppose Morals

Fortunately, not all economists are so dogmatic that they are unable to see the issue correctly. The late Fred Hirsch showed that the market economy succeed­ed because it was based on a pre-capitalist morality but its increas­ing orientation to self-interest (i.e., private-oriented behavior) at the expense of communal and public good undermined that foundation. “[T]he system,” writes Hirsch, “operated on social foundations laid under a different order of society.” But today “…it erodes the social foundations that underlie a benign and efficient implementation of the self-interest principle operating through market transactions” (Social Limits, 11). More fully he writes:

The social market economy must be the servant of humanity and of trans-economic values. All social, ethical, cultural and human values are more important than the economy, yet the economy must prepare the ground for their fullest development. For this reason the economy must not take on forms which are incompatible with these trans-economic values.

In other words, Hirsch sees another kind of social trap: One which undermines not just a particular market, but the entire free market system.

While there are undoubtedly many reasons for this, I will touch on only three. First, in so far as our national policy has been and is a commitment to endless or indefinite increases in per capita consumption, it has been a policy affirming and promoting discontent. And though in times past there was good reason to be discontent with the economy, the danger lies in cultivat­ing it as a habit of mind that is difficult, if not impossi­ble, to limit just to economics. Instead, it spills over into the social and moral spheres.

Secondly, correlated with increasing levels of consumption (discontent) is the problem of technologi­cal change. If change is too rapid and inappropriate (and in some cases, flatly immoral), it renders not only skills obsolete, which is itself demoralizing, but also entire ways of life, including the continuity we need by remembering our past, by tradition, by the wisdom and experience of parents and grandparents. Thus, individ­uals are left bobbing on an ocean of change without solid connections to an enduring community.

Thirdly, the increasing commercialization of the arts, sciences, sex, indeed every private and higher aspect of life, especially embodied in advertising, appeals to, and thereby promotes and affirms our vanity, lust, ambition, and greed. It can hardly be maintained that in such a deracinating atmosphere our characters are left unaffected.

Wilhelm Roepke

All this contributes to that “sinking in of the moral being” in Yeats’ phrase that comes with a loss of belief in higher values, virtue and morals. One result of this loss in turn is bitterness, and bitterness is always self-destructive.

Strikingly similar to Hirsch, Wilhelm Roepke pointed out “historical liberalism,” and with it especial­ly nineteenth century capitalism, failed to see that competition was not a harmless activity, either morally or psychologically, but was something that had to be kept in bounds if one wanted to avoid poison­ing the rest of society. The failure to understand this, he explained, was due to the peculiarly naive and optimistic belief “that a competitive market econo­my, based on division of labor, was an excellent moral academy which, by appealing to their self-interest, encouraged men to be pacific and decent, as well as to practice all the other civic virtues. While we know today…that competition reduces the moral stamina and therefore requires moral reserves outside the market economy.”(Social Crisis, 52) Years later, he emphasized the same point again:

The market economy is a constantly renewed texture of more or less short-lived contractual relations. It can, therefore, have no permanence unless the confidence which any contract presupposes rests on a broad and solid ethical base in all market parties. It depends upon a satisfactory average degree of personal integrity and, at the margin, upon a system of law which counteracts the natural tendency to slip back into less-than-average integrity… the ultimate moral support of the market economy lies outside the market. Market and competi­tion are far from generating their moral prerequisites autonomously… These prerequisites must be furnished from outside, and it is, on the contrary, the market and competition which constantly strain them, draw upon them, and consume them (Humane Economy, 125-6).

In figurative terms, the same explosive force of self-interest that powers the economic engine, also breaks it down, requiring interventions of adjustments and tune-ups.

To be humane as well as economically effec­tive, self-interest must be channelled and limited by the adherence of market participants to meta-economic values and that means, among other things, that we must have an idea of the end-state, the good society (which is not to be confused with utopias, either of the libertarian or Marxian variety).

Values and the End-State

At the root of this problem is the belief among the self-interest-is-enough school of economics that values and morals are purely subjective and therefore relative either to individual preferences and tastes, or to currently dominant—but more or less ephemeral—social prejudices and habits. This moral subjectivism/rela­tivism is an essential ingredient in one of the two dominant schools of liberal thought, which, in current jargon, are described as end-state liberals or procedural liberals. Norman Barry, perhaps, defines the procedur­alist school most succinctly when he states that “pro­cedural liberalism precludes the imposition on a people without their consent of any political end-state, includ­ing, of course, a liberal one.” (Barry, 112). So, the proceduralist liberal says it’s okay to end up in hell, so long as one does it “properly,” that is, according to his (subjective) notions of rules (such as free unanimous consent).

While there are ways to hedge on this, ulti­mately, this is nihilism. It is nihilistic to be indifferent to whether the free market is preserved or not, whether a free government is preserved or not. It is nihilistic to say anything goes so long as it’s done “freely.” It implies a deification of man that claims whatever he wills, collectively or individually, is all right and there is no objective value to judge or check it, nothing to validate or condemn it. To use Roepke’s phrase, it is an “intransigent dogmatism” that condemns “itself to death with open eyes… a sort of gambling club whose rules include their non-observance” (Social Crisis, 50).

We ought to have understood the danger of this sort of thinking from the Weimar experience, as Roepke and others did. The Weimar Republic boasted it had the “freest constitution” in the world, but the result of that total freedom was totalitarianism. The lesson learned was that procedures and rules themselves presuppose an enduring moral order, otherwise individ­uals will cheat on them in the familiar free-rider way. Here is another social trap, another failure of pure self-interest.

This is the conclusion drawn by other members of the Ordo-liberal school of economic thought. They learned that the expression of sound legal and economic principles could not be left to the task of irrational political and “spontaneous” economic forces. They thus came to advocate, as Norman Barry writes, a socially responsible market economy which “rejects the argu­ment that exchange itself generates an appropriate moral and welfare dimension.”(Barry, 108) They believed with Walter Eucken that “what experience of laissez-faire goes to prove is that the economic system cannot be left to organise itself” (quoted in Barry, 109). That organi­zation involves, among other things, limitations on the free­dom of contract if such a contract were, for exam­ple, to restrain competi­tion. This was seen as only logical since it was based on the “legitimisation of economic freedom in order to prevent this freedom from destroy­ing its own prerequi­sites” (quoted in Moeschel, 149).

Conclusion

The reason for many market and policy problems is the loss of those basic values and beliefs that would most effectively support the market. This problem is not removed by resorting to orthodox economics techniques and concepts, or by denying the problems exist, or by facile recommendations for government limitations and privatization. It is rather by a restoration of those values among market participants and policy-makers, a restoration which begins with the admission that self-interest alone is self-destructive and proceeds to locate economic action in the proper place in the hierarchy of human goods and in the service of a vision of the good society. As Roepke’s friend, Alexander Ruestow, put it:

The social market economy must be the servant of humanity and of trans-economic values. All social, ethical, cultural and human values are more important than the economy, yet the economy must prepare the ground for their fullest development. For this reason the economy must not take on forms which are incom­patible with these trans-economic values (quoted in Barry, 108).

Our present economy, contrary to some pro-market rhetoric, is hardly in a form compatible with “trans-economic” values. If we are not able or willing to re-cast it into such a form, we will not have to worry about communists hanging us with our own ropes… we will be doing it ourselves.

This essay in our series of “Timeless Essays” was first published here in October 2012 and it originally appeared in the Legacy of Wilhelm Roepke: Essays in Political Economy series. Copyright held by the Wilhelm Roepke Institute and reprinted here with gracious permission. Read the series’ introductory essay here. Books referenced in this essay may be found in The Imaginative Conservative Bookstore. 

References:

Norman P. Barry, “Political and Economic Thought of German Neo-Liberals,” in German Neo-Liberals and the Social Market Economy(Peacock and Willgerodt, eds.) St. Martin’s Press, New York; 1989.

Wernhard Moeschel, “Competition Policy from an Ordo Point of View,” in German Neo-Liberals and the Social Market Economy (Peacock and Willgerodt, eds.) St. Martin’s Press, New York; 1989.

Fred Hirsch, Social Limits to Growth, Har­vard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts; 1976.

Talbot Page, Conservation and Economic Efficiency, Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore and London; 1977.

Wilhelm Roepke, A Humane Economy, Henry Regnery Publishing Company, Chicago; 1960.

Wilhelm Roepke, The Social Crisis of Our Time; Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick, New Jersey; 1992 [1942].


Published: Jan 31, 2016
Author

Ralph Ancil

Dr. Ralph Ancil is the President of the Wilhelm Roepke Institute. He was a professor at Geneva College and received his Ph.D. from Michigan State University.

More articles from author

Categories: 1

0 Replies to “Essay Market Morals Related”

Leave a comment

L'indirizzo email non verrà pubblicato. I campi obbligatori sono contrassegnati *